According
to
James
Gleick,
a
tranche
of
physicists,
neuroscientists,
and
philosophers
argue
that
“free
will”
is an
illusion,
a
feeling
that
people
have
about
the
actions
they
take,
but
not
more
than
that
feeling.
He says this in a review of Free Agents: How Evolution Gave Us Free Will by Kevin J. Mitchell, a neuroscientist and geneticist at Trinity College Dublin, who has written a book-length refutation of the idea.[1] As Gleick writes, Mitchell argues that “it is neither an illusion nor merely a figure of speech. It is our essential, defining quality and as such demands explanation.” In Mitchell’s words, excerpted in the review:
We
make
decisions,
we
choose,
we
act.
These
are
the
fundamental
truths
of
our
existence
and
absolutely
the
most
basic
phenomenology
of
our
lives.
If
science
seems
to be
suggesting
otherwise,
the
correct
response
is
not
to
throw
our
hands
up
and
say,
“Well,
I
guess
everything
we
thought
about
our
own
existence
is a
laughable
delusion.”
It is
to
accept
instead
that
there
is a
deep
mystery
to be
solved
and
to
realize
that
we
may
need
to
question
the
philosophical
bedrock
of
our
scientific
approach
if we
are
to
reconcile
with
the
apparent
determinism
of
the
physical
universe.
The
declaration
that
free
will
is an
illusion
arises
from,
to me,
a
misunderstanding
of
“determinism.”
Mathematicians
and
physicists
declare
that
the
laws
of the
universe
are
set
out in
equations
that
trigger
steps
that
follow
ineluctably
one
from
the
other;
as
Gleick
says
it,
“A
determinist
believes
that
whatever
happens
had to
happen”
and
cites
Pierre-Simon
Laplace’s
declaration
that
if a
person
could
know
the
forces
acting
in
nature
on the
positions
of all
things
at a
given
instant,
“the
future
as
well
as the
past
would
be
present
to its
eyes.”
But
Mitchell’s
angle
on the
matter
puts
the
doubt
to
this
because
he
looks
at the
agency
that
creatures
have,
from
the
paramecium
to the
person,
as
coming
out of
evolutionary
necessity.
“The
universe
may
not
have a
purpose,”
he is
quoted
as
saying,
“but
life
does,”
and
the
purpose
is the
survival
of the
individual
self
in
whatever
chemical
and
electrical
form
that
that
self
has.
To
survive,
organisms
gather
information
about
the
world
around
them,
and
the
storehouse
of
information
become
the
source
for
decisions—causes
of
effects—and
while
it
might
be
possible
to say
that
the
information
determines
the
decisions,
there
is
nothing
inevitable
about
what
happens,
no
“must”
that
must
be
fulfilled.
What
defeats
the
inexorability
of the
determinists
in the
end,
according
to
Mitchell,
is the
very
world
they
say is
inexorably
driven
by
their
equations
and
laws.
When
physicists
tried
to
test
Laplace’s
hypothesis,
they
ran up
against
the
Heisenberg
uncertainty
principle,
which
exists
whether
humans
are
around
or
not,
which
means
that
there
was no
way
they
could
precisely
know
all
the
forces
acting
on all
the
objects
and
their
positions.
Schrödinger’s
equations—think
of his
poor
hapless
cat
waiting
for
the
collapse
of the
wave
function—show
an
ineradicable
indeterminacy
at the
root
of
reality.
“The
upshot
of
these
views,”
says
Mitchell,
quoted
by
Gleick,
“is
that
the
future
is
open:
indeed,
that
is
what
makes
it the
future.”
He
goes
on to
say,
If
we
could
really
glimpse
the
future,
we
would
see a
world
out
of
focus.
Not
separate
paths
already
neatly
laid
out,
waiting
to be
chosen—just
a
fuzzy,
jittery
picture
that
gets
fuzzier
and
jitterier
the
farther
into
the
future
you
look.
As
Gleick
concludes,
“He
wants
to
say,
yes,
we
live
in a
materialistic
universe;
yes,
the
laws
of
physics
apply;
yet
the
future
is not
written,
and
living
things
have
the
power
to
change
it.”
But
free
will
implies
some
kind
of
mechanism
in the
organism
that
the
organism
exercises
to
change
its
conditions.
On the
level
of a
nematode,
for
instance,
the
organism
makes
changes
in
itself
in
response
to the
conditions
in
which
it
finds
itself,
but no
one
would
argue
that
it is
exercising
a will
in
this
instance.
However,
in
more
highly
developed
organisms—us—with
our
intense
and
volatile
processing
of
information
in
both
brain
and
body
on a
moment
by
moment
basis—Mitchell
describes
it as
an
assemblage
of
“wet,
jiggly,
incomprehensibly
tiny
components
that
jitter
about
constantly”—many
of the
decisions
we
make—maybe
even
most—are
made
without
any
conscious
exercise
of
governance:
we
breathe,
digest,
and so
on
without
the
executive
function
of the
brain
sending
a
communique
to the
appropriate
parts
of the
body.
This
high
degree
of
involuntary
action
in our
day-to-day
quest
to
survive
seems
to
prove
to
what
Gleick
calls
“the
free-will
deniers”
that
action
and
conscious
will
do not
coincide,
and
that
conscious
will,
rather
than
being
a
process
employed
by us
to do
something,
is
just a
way to
describe
an experience of acting as a person who acts, not an actual historical deed:
in
other
words,
a
delusion.
But
as
both
Gleick
and
Mitchell
point
out,
the
human
encounter
with
acting
is
deeper
and
richer
than
the
description
of a
creature
propelled
by
hapless
forward
motion
offered
by the
free-will
deniers.
Mitchell
calls
it a
“more
naturalized
concept
of the
self,”
a self
that
is an
entire
organism
with a
set of
embodied
histories
that
must
be
understood
as a
whole.
To
quote
Gleick:
We
do
things
for
reasons
based
on
our
histories,
and
“those
reasons
inhere
at
the
level
of
the
whole
organism.”
Much
of
the
time,
perhaps
most
of
the
time,
our
conscious
self
is
not
in
control.
Still,
when
the
occasion
requires,
we
can
gather
our
wits,
as
the
expression
goes.
We
have
so
many
expressions
like
that—get a grip; pull yourself together; focus your thoughts—metaphors
for
the
indistinct
things
we
see
when
we
look
inward.
We
don’t
ask
who
is
gathering
whose
wits.
As
Gleick
describes
the
working
of
Mitchell’s
“more
naturalized
concept
of the
self,”
our
cerebral
cortex
comes
up
with
options,
always
subject
to
fluctuations
and
noise;
the
brain
then
evaluates
these
options
(up-voting
and
down-voting
among
its
various
regions)
based
on
goals
and
beliefs
built
from
experience,
stored
in
memory,
and
more
or
less
malleable;
and
all
this
is
mediated
by the
representations
of
self
that
we
have
built
up
over
time
through
the
countless
instances
of
engaging
with
the
world
in
order
to
survive.
To
quote
Mitchell:
The
various
subsystems
involved
are
in
constant
dialogue
with
each
other,
each
attempting
to
satisfy
its
own
constraints
in
the
context
of
the
dynamically
changing
information
it
receives
from
all
the
other
interconnected
areas.
Not at all a passive shuttlecock badmintoned around by the laws of physics.
So,
why
would
there
such
an
effort
at
this
historical
time
and
place
to
deny
that
humans
are as
they
are?
Good
question,
escritor.
If
we can
plot
“free
will”
on a
continuum
from
left
to
right,
with
one
end
being
no
free
will
(that
is, no
capacity
for
independent
decision-making)
and
the
other
being,
well,
God
(the
ability
to
make
any
decision
at any
time
about
anything
and
make
it
stick),
the
leftmost
station
would
be
occupied
by
Robert
Sapolsky,
who in Determined:
A
Science
of
Life
without
Free
Will,
published
last
year,
states
that
humans
have
no
free
will,
none
whatsoever.
Everything
I do
has
been
determined
since
the
Big
Bang:
“We
are
nothing
more
or
less
than
the
cumulative
biological
and
environmental
luck,
over
which
we had
no
control,
that
has
brought
us to
any
moment.”
The
problem
with
this,
of
course,
politically
speaking,
is
that
those
who
believe
that
history
equals
biology
will
then
use
that
equation
to
argue
that
the
way
things
are is
the
way
they
should
be.
Following
from
that,
then,
is
that
any
effort
to
“correct”
things
are
patently
wrong
and
thus
can be
legitimately
repressed.
On the
right,
this
is the
land
of
Social
Darwinism
and
eugenics
and
racialist
ethnographies
(i.e.,
white
is
right).
On the
left,
it is
the
land
of
identarian
politics
and
orthodoxies
about
systemic
oppression.
In
other
words,
going
down
the
Sapolsky
road
can
end in
a
society
where
everyone
is
slotted,
and
their
fates
are
foreordained.
A
world
frozen
into
its
categories
in
which
Hobbes’
state
of
every
man
against
every
man
for
control
of
resources
becomes
the
daily
grind.
But
just
because
Sapolsky
argues
that
his
science
says
what
it
says
doesn’t
mean
that
humans
have
to
accept
it at
all
and
can
argue
and
mobilize
against
it.
Now,
Sapolsky
might
counter
that
that
resistance
is
also
fated,
but he
cannot
deny
that
the
resistance
changes
things
because
whenever
humans
act
upon
the
world
in
which
they
live,
they
change
things—in
other
words,
they
make
the
world
indeterminate.
Again,
Sapolsky
might
argue
that
that
“indeterminacy”
is
itself
determined
by all
the
prior
activity,
but at
this
point,
it’s
clear
that
the
concept
of
determinacy,
by
trying
to
explain
everything,
explains
nothing
and
therefore
obligates
no one
to
believe
in it
and
act
upon
its
principles.
Mitchell
points
out
that
the
physicists
point
out
that
indeterminacy
rules
in
reality.
Now,
introducing
an
element
of
indeterminacy
or
randomness
or
unpredictability
into
the
system
doesn’t
guarantee
that
the
organisms
in
that
reality
have
free
will,
but it
opens
up
space
for
such a
thing
to
exist
and be
exercised.
So,
what
is
this
free
will
we’re
talking
about?
First,
I
would
drop
the
adjective
“free”—there
is
only
“will,”
that
is,
the
power
to
make a
choice
to
make
something
happen
in the
world.
I
think
will
means
two
things.
One is
what
is
described
above:
a
process
of
gathering
wits
where,
at the
end of
the
process,
the
human
makes
a
choice
to
take a
path
(right
or
wrong
is not
important
here;
the
fact
of the
choosing is).
I
think
the
second
element
of
will
is
resistance.
Determinacy
and
indeterminacy
are
both
equally
threatening
to the
human
organism,
and
will
as
resistance
is the
attempt
by the
human
to
bring
clarity
out of
the
chaos
and
ensure
safety
for
itself,
a
process
that
is
both
necessary
and
neverending.
In
the
exercise
of its
will,
the
human
changes
the
world.
This
is not
just a
philosophical
statement
but a
statement
rooted
in
biology—just
not
Sapolsky’s
biology.
Our
brain/bodies
(our
conjoined
subsystems,
as
Mitchell
describes
them)
are
built,
as far
as we
can
tell,
like
no
other
organism
on the
earth:
we
create
realities
that
do not
“exist”
to our
fingertips
but
yet do
exist
and
exert
influence
upon
us—paracosms,
fictions,
languages,
cultures,
and so
on—that
have
resculpted
the
planet
and
outpaced
natural
selection.
We
exert
will
all
the
time,
if by
will
we
mean
the
power
to
reshape
and
redeploy
reality,
but
that
will
also
has a
continuum,
from
the
autonomic
to the
life-or-death.
Sometimes
that
will,
as
Mitchell
notes,
is not
directly
guided
by or
available
to us,
such
as
automatic
breathing
or
digestion.
But
the
truth
is, I
don’t
need
to be
aware
of
those
decisions
being
made,
just
as I
don’t
need
to
know
all
the
subroutines
being
run in
my
word
processing
program
as I
type
out
this
essay.
I just
need
them
to
work
so
that I
can
attend
to the
life-or-death
things
at the
other
end of
the
continuum.
Of
course,
we can
believe
what
Sapolsky
peddles,
but
there’s
no
gain
for
human
happiness
or
security
in
doing
so.
Humans
are a
dynamic
element
in the
life
of the
planet,
and
what
we
humans
do or
don’t
do has
consequences.
We can
box
ourselves
in by
determinacy
and
relieve
ourselves
of
moral
responsibility
or we
can
will
ourselves
to act
in a
way
that
honors
freedom,
creativity,
empathy,
purpose,
and
all
the
other
values
that
give
human
life
its
strange
and
seductive
beauty.
Yes,
we can
be
cruel,
selfish,
deadly,
barbaric
as
well
as
honorable,
loving,
generous,
sweet,
but we
are
not fated to be any of these—they are all the result of choices we make within systems we create on a planet that responds to what we do. This does not mean that the “we” in that sentence is something like a pilot in a cockpit, a master of destiny. But neither is it an autopilot following an algorithm. As Gleick says in his review:
Even
on
our
best
days
we’re
subject
to
delusions
and
confusion.
We
act
without
thinking,
from
habit
or
reflex
or
instinct.
We
behave
impulsively,
for
no
reasons
we
can
discern.
Yet
unconscious
decision-making
is
still
decision-making.
And
sometimes
we do
think.
We
reflect,
ponder,
dither,
weigh
alternatives
for
some
time
before
choosing
to
act.
Humans
make
their
own
destinies,
though,
as
Karl
Marx
pointed
out,
it’s
a
tricky
dance
to
balance
“the
tradition
of all
dead
generations”
with
“creating
something
that
did
not
exist
before”—but
we do
do
this,
all
the
time,
and it
will
be a
tragedy
to let
Sapolsky
and
others
trick
us out
of
exercising
our
freedom
to
express
our
will.
[1] New York Review of Books, Jan. 18, 2024.
|